Wednesday, September 29, 2010
Monday, September 27, 2010
Karl Popper (1902 - 1994)
Karl Popper is generally regarded as one of the greatest philosophers of science of the 20th century. He was also a social and political philosopher of considerable stature, a self-professed ‘critical-rationalist’, a dedicated opponent of all forms of scepticism, conventionalism, and relativism in science and in human affairs generally, a committed advocate and staunch defender of the ‘Open Society’, and an implacable critic of totalitarianism in all of its forms. One of the many remarkable features of Popper's thought is the scope of his intellectual influence
Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889 - 1951)
Considered by some to be the greatest philosopher of the 20th century, Ludwig Wittgenstein played a central, if controversial, role in 20th-century analytic philosophy. He continues to influence current philosophical thought in topics as diverse as logic and language, perception and intention, ethics and religion, aesthetics and culture.
There are two commonly recognized stages of Wittgenstein's thought — the early and the later — both of which are taken to be pivotal in their respective periods.
The early Wittgenstein is epitomized in his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. By showing the application of modern logic to metaphysics, via language, he provided new insights into the relations between world, thought and language and thereby into the nature of philosophy.
It is the later Wittgenstein, mostly recognized in the Philosophical Investigations, who took the more revolutionary step in critiquing all of traditional philosophy including its climax in his own early work. The nature of his new philosophy is heralded as anti-systematic through and through, yet still conducive to genuine philosophical understanding of traditional problems.
Labels:
analytic,
critical philosophy,
culture,
ethics,
intention,
investigations,
language,
logic,
Ludwig Wittgenstein,
methaphysics,
perception,
religion,
revolutionary
Immanuel Kant (1724–1804)
Is the central figure in modern philosophy. He synthesized early modern rationalism and empiricism, set the terms for much of nineteenth and twentieth century philosophy, and continues to exercise a significant influence today in metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, political philosophy, aesthetics, and other fields. The fundamental idea of Kant's “critical philosophy”.
He argues that the human understanding is the source of the general laws of nature that structure all our experience; and that human reason gives itself the moral law, which is our basis for belief in God, freedom, and immortality. Therefore, scientific knowledge, morality, and religious belief are mutually consistent and secure because they all rest on the same foundation of human autonomy, which is also the final end of nature according to the teleological worldview of reflecting judgment that Kant introduces to unify the theoretical and practical parts of his philosophical system.
Labels:
critical philosophy,
Early Modern,
empiricism,
epistemology,
ethics,
experience,
freedom,
Immanuel,
immortality,
Kant,
knowledge,
methaphysics,
morality,
nature,
rationalism
David Hume (1711 - 1776)
The last of the great triumvirate of “British empiricists” — was also well-known in his own time as an historian and essayist. A master stylist in any genre, Hume's major philosophical works — A Treatise of Human Nature (1739-1740), the Enquiries concerning Human Understanding (1748) and concerning the Principles of Morals (1751), as well as the posthumously published Dialogues concerning Natural Religion (1779) — remain widely and deeply influential.
Although many of Hume's contemporaries denounced his writings as works of scepticism and atheism, his influence is evident in the moral philosophy and economic writings of his close friend Adam Smith. Hume also awakened Immanuel Kant from his “dogmatic slumbers” and “caused the scales to fall” from Jeremy Bentham's eyes. Charles Darwin counted Hume as a central influence, as did “Darwin's bulldog,” Thomas Henry Huxley. The diverse directions in which these writers took what they gleaned from reading Hume reflect not only the richness of their sources but also the wide range of his empiricism. Today, philosophers recognize Hume as a precursor of contemporary cognitive science, as well as one of the most thoroughgoing exponents of philosophical naturalism.
Friday, September 24, 2010
Leibniz (1646 - 1716)
German philosopher, mathematician, historian and jurist, contemporary of Newton (1642-1727), with whom he feuded bitterly over the invention of calculus. Although Gottfried Leibniz left behind no philosophical magnum opus, he is still considered to be among the giant thinkers of the 17th-century. Leibniz believed in "pre-established harmony" between the outer world and maind, and developed a philosophy of Rationalism by which he attempted to reconcile the existence of matter with the existence of God. Bertrand Russel wrote that Leibniz's intellect "was highly abstract and logical; his greatest claim to fame is as an inventor of the infinitesimal calculus
Leibniz's reflections on epistemological matters do not rival his reflections on logic, metaphysics, divine justice, and natural philosophy in terms of quantity. Nevertheless, he did think deeply about the possibility and nature of human knowledge, and his main doctrines
Spinoza (1632 - 1677)
Spinoza is one of the most important philosophers—and certainly the most radical—of the early modern period. His thought combines a commitment to Cartesian metaphysical and epistemological principles with elements from ancient Stoicism and medieval Jewish rationalism into a nonetheless highly original system. His extremely naturalistic views on God, the world, the human being and knowledge serve to ground a moral philosophy centered on the control of the passions leading to virtue and happiness. They also lay the foundations for a strongly democratic political thought and a deep critique of the pretensions of Scripture and sectarian religion. Of all the philosophers of the seventeenth-century, perhaps none have more relevance today than Spinoza.
—His ethics are very similar to Aristotle’s in content and in being eudemonistic.
—He holds a reductionist and arguably naturalistic understanding of the human being.
—He denies the freedom of the will and transcendent values.
—He tends to subsume the practical under the theoretical.
Method of Epistemology:
The admission that there are a variety of ways one can have knowledge.
There is a definitively adequate way for knowing this variety of ways.
—Spinoza’s method has two aspects; one that is formal and another that is more concerned with the concrete perspectives that define the different ways one can have knowledge.
The admission that there are a variety of ways one can have knowledge.
There is a definitively adequate way for knowing this variety of ways.
—Spinoza’s method has two aspects; one that is formal and another that is more concerned with the concrete perspectives that define the different ways one can have knowledge.
Knowledge — :
Adequate vs. Inadequate ideas
3 Types of knowledge
-Imagination: disorganized accumulation of experience
- Reason : logical deductions made based on an understanding of the nature of space (e.g. geometry) or of the nature of thought (e.g. logic, psychology)
-intuition: the intuitive grasp of a particular thing on the basics of ration
3 Types of knowledge
-Imagination: disorganized accumulation of experience
- Reason : logical deductions made based on an understanding of the nature of space (e.g. geometry) or of the nature of thought (e.g. logic, psychology)
-intuition: the intuitive grasp of a particular thing on the basics of ration
—The polemic against traditional ethics:
-Against free will
-Against absolute normative terms
-Against teleology —The naturalistic replacement:
-The human being as conatus
-The redefinition of “freedom,” “good,” and “bad”
-A special brand of hedonism
-Resemblance to Aristotelian virtue ethics
-Akrasia and moral knowledge
Labels:
adequate,
Aristotelian,
Early Modern,
ethics,
eudemonistic,
imagination,
inadequate,
intuition,
knowledge,
methaphysics,
naturalistic,
practical,
reason,
Spinoza
Rene Descartes (1595-1650)
Rene Descartes was a famous French mathematician, scientist and philosopher. He was arguably the first major philosopher in the modern era to make a serious effort to defeat skepticism. His views about knowledge and certainty, as well as his views about the relationship between mind and body have been very influential over the last three centuries.
Descartes understands doubt as the contrast of certainty. As my certainty increases, my doubt decreases; conversely, as my doubt increases, my certainty decreases. The requirement that knowledge is to be based in complete, or perfect certainty, amounts to requiring a complete absence of doubt — an indubitability, or inability to undermine one's conviction. Descartes' methodic emphasis on doubt, rather than on certainty, marks an epistemological innovation. This so-called ‘method of doubt’
Descartes understands doubt as the contrast of certainty. As my certainty increases, my doubt decreases; conversely, as my doubt increases, my certainty decreases. The requirement that knowledge is to be based in complete, or perfect certainty, amounts to requiring a complete absence of doubt — an indubitability, or inability to undermine one's conviction. Descartes' methodic emphasis on doubt, rather than on certainty, marks an epistemological innovation. This so-called ‘method of doubt’
Labels:
certainty,
decreases,
Descartes,
doubt,
French,
increases,
indubitability,
influential,
innovation,
knowledge,
mathematician,
method of doubt,
modern era,
philosopher,
Rene,
scientist,
skepticism
William Ockham (1287 - 1347)
William of Ockham is, along with Thomas Aquinas and John Duns Scotus, among the most prominent figures in the history of philosophy during the High Middle Ages. He is probably best known today for his espousal of metaphysical nominalism; indeed, the methodological principle known as “Ockham's Razor” is named after him. But Ockham held important, often influential views not only in metaphysics but also in all other major areas of medieval philosophy—logic, physics or natural philosophy, theory of knowledge, ethics, and political philosophy—as well as in theology.
Ockham's is not much concerned with answering skeptical doubts. He takes it for granted that humans not only can but frequently do know things, and focuses his attention instead on the “mechanisms” by which this knowledge comes about. Ockham's theory of knowledge, like his natural philosophy, is broadly Aristotelian in form, although—again, like his natural philosophy—it is “Aristotelian” in its own way. For most Aristotelians of the day, knowledge involved the transmission of a “species” between the object and the mind. At the sensory level, this species may be compared to the more recent notion of a sense “impression.”
Aristotle (384 - 322 BCE)
Born at Stagira in northern Greece, Aristotle was the most notable product of the educational program devised by Plato; he spent twenty years of his life studying at the Academy. When Plato died, Aristotle returned to his native Macedonia, where he is supposed to have participated in the education of Philip's son, Alexander (the Great). He came back to Athens with Alexander's approval in 335 and established his own school at the Lyceum, spending most of the rest of his life engaged there in research, teaching, and writing. His students acquired the name "peripatetics" from the master's habit of strolling about as he taught.
Aristotelic knowledge :
Sensation is the passive capacity for the soul to be changed through the contact of the associated body with external objects.
Thought is the more active process of engaging in the manipulation of forms without any contact with external objects at all.
Desire is the origin of movement toward some goal.
Plato (427—347 BCE)
Plato is one of the world’s best known and most widely read and studied philosophers. He was the student of Socrates and the teacher ofAristotle, and he wrote in the middle of the fourth century B.C.E. in ancient Greece. Though influenced primarily by Socrates, to the extent that Socrates is usually the main character in many of Plato’s writings, he was also influenced by Heraclitus, Parmenides, and the Pythagoreans.
Platonic epistemology holds that knowledge is innate, so that learning is the development of ideas buried deep in the soul, often under the midwife-like guidance of an interrogator. Plato believed that each soul existed before birth with "The Form of the Good" and a perfect knowledge of everything. Thus, when something is "learned" it is actually just "recalled."
Wednesday, September 22, 2010
Epistemology - Subtopics
- Accessibilism : The position that whether someone's belief is justified supervenes only on facts to which that person has some sort of access.
- Epistemic injustice: Principle that when one is not believed for prejudicial reasons one is wronged epistemically. Primarily advanced by British philosopher Miranda Fricker.
- Internalism and externalism: Names of two contrasting theories in several areas of philosophy, Internalism has a variety of different meanings within philosophy, and for each of these meanings there is a corresponding externalist position which is just the denial of the internalist one.
- Knowledge: On one common account by philosophers, justified, true belief; often used in a looser way by everyone else to mean any truth or belief, and also a whole body of truth or a whole system of belief.
- Mentalism : The position that whether someone's belief is justified supervenes only on their mental states.
- Philosophical skepticism: Rejection of the possibility of knowledge.
- Rating raw intelligence: The process, before intelligence analysis, in which intelligence collection managers rate individual items of "raw" collected data for plausibility and reliability
- Reliabilism : The theory that a belief is justified, or a true belief is known, if it is the product of a reliable process.
Labels:
accessibilism,
belief,
epistemology,
externalism,
facts,
intelligence,
knowledge,
materialism,
mentalism,
philosophical,
principle,
reliabilism,
skepticism,
truth
Purpose
- Analyzing the nature of knowledge and how it relates to connected notions such as truth, belief, and justification.
- Deals with the means of production of knowledge, as well as skepticism about different knowledge claims.
Tuesday, September 21, 2010
Basic Questions
- What is knowledge? That is, what counts as knowledge as opposed to belief or opinion?
a) beliefs which are true for which we can give justification
- 2. Can we have knowledge? Are human beings capable of knowing anything?
a) Skepticism - "No!"
b) Dogmatism - "Yes!"
- 3. How do we get knowledge? What is the process by which knowledge is obtained?
a) Rationalism - through reason alone
b) Empiricism - through the senses alone
- 4. What can we know?
a) What ever we want to know.
- 5. How can we know it?
a) Through reason
- 6. Why do we know some things, but not others?
a) Because our reason or our senses, don’t perceive it
- 7. Is knowledge possible?
a) Skepticism - "No!"
b) Dogmatism - "Yes!"
- 8. Can knowledge be certain?
a) Yes. It is acquired through experience.
- 9. How can we differentiate truth from falsehood?
a) The truth will always provide us those beliefs that have real justification of facts.
- 10. Why do we believe certain claims and not others?
a) Because we have the proof and knowledge of certain claims and according to our knowledge we can deduct which claims are truth or not.
Sunday, September 19, 2010
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)